Skip to main content

Rousseau’s Theory of the Natural Man and A Criticism of Locke’s “Social” Man

A criticism that Jean-Jacques Rousseau levies against John Locke and the liberal tradition, is the conceptual origin of man in the state of nature, in which he addresses the lack of pinpointing the true, natural man that has become the template for Locke and others in legitimizing the need of civil society. Rousseau makes the claim that that their “natural man” is nothing but a “social man” and that they have not gone further in time to make a legitimate assessment of the true, natural man. Rousseau boldly claims that Locke has misinterpreted social man as natural man, but even goes to great lengths to demonstrate that he has been able to discover the true attributes of man in nature, and develops his argument on the perversion that is the forming of the civil society and the implications on man. For Rousseau, natural man is broken down, to where he de-personifies man into a beast—the opposite for Locke and the liberal tradition, which creates a natural man with social elements, like language and reason—that for Rousseau is only attainable through a civil society. The two principles of the natural man prior to reason (which differentiates social man, from natural man), are self-preservation and pity.[1] His element of a bestial man (vis-à-vis, the questioning timeframe of which “man” to interpret and the aspects of the natural man) and the regard of pity are critically important, for it brings in the natural, humanistic concepts that Locke and the liberal tradition have overlooked.
For John Locke, man in the state of nature is guided by the concept of reason and that because of the need of self-preservation came into conflict with biased adjudication, a civil society came into fruition.[2] This idea of man having reason in the state of nature is a very controversial perspective of the natural man, seeing as Rousseau questions whether or not the natural man had the capacity to have any reason or to form a connection to other fellow human beings. With this in mind, he ponders how far back is needed to go, to come face-to-face with the natural man. For Rousseau, Locke and tradition have looked at the wrong type of man, at the wrong time in history. His take is,
The philosophers, who have inquired into the foundations of society, have all felt the necessity of going back to a state of nature, but not one of them has got there…Every one of them, in short, constantly dwelling on wants, avidity, oppression, desires, and pride, has transferred to the state of nature ideas which were acquired in society; so that, in speaking of the savage, they described the social man.[3]
Rousseau is wary to label natural man in the same fashion that Locke and others have done. He is being guided by the notion that not only does government have to be stripped to get to the natural man, but bring man to the simplest form capable, that of a beast. He has no empirical evidence for this[4], but this is an experiment to develop his argument of the natural man being a “noble savage,” and trying to hinder the legitimacy of the civil society and its purpose. By describing Locke’s “natural man” as “social man,” is to look at the basic elements that Locke left man before he entered civil society. Rousseau sees Locke’s superficial preservation of the self through adjudication and property as the disqualifier for being the natural man. Rousseau writes,
Thus, as every man punished the contempt shown him by others, in proportion to his opinion of himself, revenge became terrible, and men bloody and cruel. This is precisely the state reached by most of the savage nations known to us: and it is for want of having made a proper distinction in our ideas, and see how very far they already are from the state of nature, that so many writers have hastily concluded that man is naturally cruel, and requires civil institutions to make him more mild; whereas nothing is more gentle than man in his primitive state, as he is placed by nature at an equal distance from the stupidity of brutes, and the fatal ingenuity of civilized man.[5]
Rousseau, through the above quote, simply summarizes the logic used by the “writers” (Locke) to conclude that the natural man is something to fear. Instead of doing what they were supposed to do, which is to look at the natural man, they have actually placed the civilized man in the state of nature, and this leads to the misinterpretation of what truly is the natural, simplistic man.  
            To understand this criticism of not only looking at the right man and the right time is to look at it metaphorically. To know man, is to break down man, and to see that it has changed like a statue that has been altered by nature, through various means.[6] The pursuit of knowledge and experiences has severed the connection between the primitive state and the civilized man, which calls for a simplistic perspective, in order to get to the original creation. This is where Rousseau comes in, and where Locke is nowhere to be found. The bare necessities of man, or the bestial man, are the theory that will yield the true attributes of the natural man. As mentioned before, the two principles of man are self-preservation and pity, but Locke and the liberal tradition do not account for the element of pity at all. Preservation is the fundamental key for Locke in coming out of the state of nature, as is for others, but the idea of pity is brushed aside, and Rousseau thinks this leads to the miscalculation of the natural man being something to fear at, without really putting those two elements side-by-side; noting that both of these creates humanity and virtue.[7] Rousseau examines pity by stating that man “is restrained by natural compassion from doing any injury to others…and that the very brutes themselves sometimes give evident proofs of it.”[8] By this argument, Rousseau is beginning to break away from the war-like state that Locke and the tradition attributes to man. Without no laws (and a civil society), pity is the natural feeling that moderates the activities of love in the self and the continuation of man.[9]
            From the two principles of the natural man, he then breaks the state of nature even further, into the physical, metaphysical, and moral aspects of man to get to the original creation. For Rousseau, the natural man is built with faculties of strength and agility (physical aspect)[10], with the ability of perfectibility (metaphysical aspect)[11], and a confinement of passions to his physical wants (moral aspects)[12]. Thus for Rousseau, the natural man is simply free in his capabilities, but is endowed with the ability to perfect himself;
Nature lays her commands on every animal, and the brute obeys her voice. Man receives the same impulsion, but at the same time knows himself at liberty to acquiesce or resist: and it is particularly in his consciousness of this liberty that the spirituality of his soul is displayed.[13]
Yet, if the difficulties attending all these questions should still leave room for dispute about this difference between men and brutes, there is another very specific quality which distinguishes them, and which will admit of no dispute. This is the faculty of self-improvement, which, by the help of circumstances, gradually develops all the rest of our faculties, and is inherent in the species as in the individual: whereas a brute is, at the end of a few months, all he will ever be during his whole life.[14]
Through both quotes, comes the understanding of whether or not man is inherently evil (or biased) as portrayed by Locke and the tradition. He has outlined throughout his “experiment” that the natural man is being guided by self-preservation and pity, endowed with certain aspects, and underlying this is the realization that the natural man has the capacity to change; the idea of perfectibility. This concept gives rise to the notion that man can become something different from what they were at creation, meaning that through experiences and knowledge, man has been able to change for the better good or bad as a whole (and the individual). Locke and the liberal tradition do not account for this, for they see man in a fixed state, and see civil society as the only means to suppress their “natural” inclinations. Rousseau’s criticism is then asserting that the bestial element has been able to evolve, with the two principles clashing, and that Locke and the liberal tradition have only legitimized the civil society for the corrupt, social man. 


[1] Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, p. 47.
[2] Locke, John. The Second Treatise of Government and a Letter Concerning Toleration. New York: Macmillan, 2002. Print, Book II; §19; §95.

[3] Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, p. 50.
[4] Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, p. 50.
[5] Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, p. 90.
[6] Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, pp. 58-59.
[7] Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, p. 73.
[8] Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, p. 73.
[9] Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, p. 76
[10] Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, pp. 53-59.
[11] Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, pp. 59-60.
[12] Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, p. 61.
[13] Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, p. 60.
[14] Rousseau, Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, p. 60. 

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Re-Post "Marriage Equality, Immigration, and … Fraud?"

This article comes from Concurring Opinions  (a group blog on legal topics), posted by Kerry Abrams. Very interesting article/post concerning DOMA's invalidation of Section 3, and what it means for binational same-sex couples when it comes to their marriage and immigration. Marriage Equality, Immigration, and … Fraud? posted by Kerry Abrams The demise of DOMA may mean that same-sex married couples are now entitled to the same marriage-based immigration benefits as anyone else. But marriage equality also entails equal burdens. As I argued in Immigration Law and the Regulation of Marriage, 91 Minn. L. Rev. 1625 (2007), immigration law holds marriages involving immigrants to a higher standard than the law ordinarily demands, and this will now be true for same-sex couples. Under state family law, married people are not required to live together. They don’t have to open joint bank accounts, jointly own property, take extensive vacation photos, document which guests attended ...

Favorite Lines/Quotes from Sophocles' AJAX

      Well then, now you’ve seen his arrogance,       make sure you never speak against the gods,       or give yourself ideas of your own grandeur,       if your strength of hand or heaped-up riches                                     [130]       should outweigh some other man’s. A single day       pulls down any human’s scale of fortune       or raises it once more.  But the gods love                              170       m...