Skip to main content

The Senate and Use of the Filibuster

The United States Senate has one of the most powerful tools known in a democracy; the use of the filibuster. The filibuster is a way to simply extend debate, primarily used by the minority party in the Senate, to limit or halt the procession of a bill sponsored by the majority. It is seen as a protection, and it distinguishes the Senate from the House. The use of the filibuster arises by the Senate’s authority to determine its own procedures and rules outlined by the U.S. Constitution, Article I, Section 5. However, since the 70s, the use of invoking a filibuster has more than increased bringing into question the constitutionality of it and the gridlock in getting anything done that seems to go with it. However, this problem was addressed early in the 20th Century with the adoption of Rule 22, which introduces the motion of cloture, where the Senate by a 60 member vote can overstep the filibuster and proceed with the bill. The articles by Gerhardt, Koger, and Binder tackle the problems of the filibuster, the history, and the needed reforms to either do away with tradition, or to introduce a limit of the uses of it. They are able to make the case that a reform is needed badly. In this 112th Congress, the Democrats (the current majority) are about to enter into talks of reforming the use of the filibuster, while the Republicans (the minority party) voice their discontent; just as in 2005 when the Republicans who were in control, threatened a similar reform with the nuclear option that ended up going nowhere.
In the article by Chaftez/Gerhardt, a discussion is talked about whether or not the filibuster is constitutional, particularly paying attention to the super-majority needed to invoke cloture. Josh Chafetz makes the point that “cloture has now effectively become a requirement for passage of any significant measure.”[1] He goes on to a specific paragraph that shows the history of the increase of the rise of filibusters and how successful the Senate has been in invoking cloture. He notes that the increase in filibusters has increased dramatically since the 1970s, and that the filibuster is diverting from its original purpose of halting controversial bills, to anything that a Senator feels doesn’t need to be passed for no reason whatsoever.[2] He introduces an opposing view of his analysis of the current use of the filibuster, by saying that supporters may cite history and the longevity of the filibuster, but he argues that the association that comes with the term “filibuster” is simply a pseudo notion, seeing as no debate is taken place and that it is simply a “permanent minority obstruction”[3] that has evolved into an unconstitutional procedure. Michael Gerhardt refutes Chaftez’s attack on the super-majority needed to end a filibuster, by agreeing that there is a problem with the increase uses of the filibuster, but withholds calling the institution of the filibuster and the needed majority as deciphered by the Senate, unconstitutional.[4] He sees the problem as “the Senate [lacking] a majority genuinely committed to challenging abuses of Senate procedures”[5] and that just because it has become tedious for the American public, does not mean it is by any chance unconstitutional. He urges and ends his argument, that the Senate has the authority vested by the Constitution to continue with the use of the filibuster, as long as they are able to carry out the implied powers they have been assigned. If it continues, to where nothing is able to be achieved, he closes his rebuttal by saying that the solution to clear the gridlock is through the electoral process.[6]  
It may seem that that super-majority through the 60 member vote is the degree to which a bill can be passed, however, it was much harder prior to 1975, in which the cloture was only able to be invoked by two-thirds of the Senate, or 67 votes.[7] The reform of cloture through the Senate’s history from 1918, the year the rule was adopted, to around the 1980s is methodically analyzed by Gregory Koger in the relationship between the majority in control and the likelihood of a reform. He notes through his research that “although a united majority could impose new limits on obstruction, it is difficult for senators to form coalitions that have a strong common interest in cloture reform, particularly majority cloture.”[8] Getting this fixed is a matter of bipartisanship, and it is very difficult when the Senate is highly polarized as it has become. A prime example of this is analyzed by Binder, in which she cites the pivotal cry of the Republicans during their domination of the Senate in 2005, before they lost control in 2007, with the nuclear option they threatened at the Democrats who kept Bush’s nominations to the federal courts at bay.[9] The nominations were not getting anywhere, so they wanted to do away with the filibuster, but to do that, as Koger mentioned, coalitions needed to be established before any reform could take place, seeing as a reform for a Senate procedure/rule requires a super-majority, and the Democrats were not willing to give up without a fight.
The articles are able to convey the diminishing effect of the filibuster, and the proposed reforms that seem to veer off into obscurity, seeing as the procedure is something that both parties want to use if they should ever find themselves in the minority, but when they are on the majority side, they want a way to bypass the obstructions to get their agenda passed. If they want to retain tradition, and make the Senate work again, the public needs to be swayed by each party to use their vote to change this gridlock, for the majority to have more than the required 60 votes, as Gerhardt argued. However, the point that Chaftez makes on the term and original purpose of the filibuster is important, because he provides a clear solution to limit the uses of it, by proposing that if a Senator wishes to filibuster a bill, they should talk the bill to death as long as they are able to. This could in fact, limit the filibuster to bills that are controversial, and see the Senate pass legislations that are not as controversial. Limiting the reform to only the cloture is not enough, without taking into account the main underlying problem that has caused the gridlock, the filibuster itself.
Sources:
Gerhardt, Michael J. and Chafetz, Josh, Is the Filibuster Constitutional? (September 18, 2011). University of Pennsylvania Law Review, Vol. 158, pp. 245-267, 201.
Koger, Greg. “Cloture Reform and Party Government in the Senate, 1918-1921.” Journal of Politics 68:3 (2006): 708-719.
Sarah A. Binder, Anthony J. Madonna and Steven S. Smith (2007). Going Nuclear, Senate Style. Perspectives on Politics, 5, pp 729-740.




[1] Chaftez, 247-248.
[2] Chaftez,  248-249.
[3] Chaftez, 250.
[4] Gerhardt, 253.
[5] Gerhardt, 253.
[6] Gerhardt,  267.
[7] Koger, 708; 712-713.
[8] Koger, 717-718.
[9] Sarah Binder, 735-736. 

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Re-Post "Marriage Equality, Immigration, and … Fraud?"

This article comes from Concurring Opinions  (a group blog on legal topics), posted by Kerry Abrams. Very interesting article/post concerning DOMA's invalidation of Section 3, and what it means for binational same-sex couples when it comes to their marriage and immigration. Marriage Equality, Immigration, and … Fraud? posted by Kerry Abrams The demise of DOMA may mean that same-sex married couples are now entitled to the same marriage-based immigration benefits as anyone else. But marriage equality also entails equal burdens. As I argued in Immigration Law and the Regulation of Marriage, 91 Minn. L. Rev. 1625 (2007), immigration law holds marriages involving immigrants to a higher standard than the law ordinarily demands, and this will now be true for same-sex couples. Under state family law, married people are not required to live together. They don’t have to open joint bank accounts, jointly own property, take extensive vacation photos, document which guests attended

Favorite Lines/Quotes from Sophocles' AJAX

      Well then, now you’ve seen his arrogance,       make sure you never speak against the gods,       or give yourself ideas of your own grandeur,       if your strength of hand or heaped-up riches                                     [130]       should outweigh some other man’s. A single day       pulls down any human’s scale of fortune       or raises it once more.  But the gods love                              170       men who possess good sense and self-control       and despise the ones who are unjust. I’m just as strong,       with the work of my own hands I have attained       achievements just as great, but, as you see,       these Argive insults have quite ruined me.                                        [440]       And yet I think I can affirm this much—       had Achilles lived and been about to judge       the man who should receive his weapons,       the prize for being the finest man in war,       no soldier would have put his hand on them